Sex, Sacrament, and Civil Society
In a world so flooded with sexual
images and energies that it has reached a Brave New Level of boredom, it seems
only the eccentricities retain any possibility to excite. Hence our current seeming fascination with
such matters as “same-sex marriage.” In
the last few years, some have insisted that we should ban same-sex marriage by
legislative fiat. Most recently, this
country’s highest court has taken the opposite approach by banning any and all
such bans by its own judicial fiat
But, as usual, they are all wrong. Or at least, that is not the whole story.
That cannot be the whole story because
to presume that it is such is to hold to the fallacious belief that marriage is
a mere human creation of positive law: the Supreme Court decision treated the
issuing of marriage licenses as if it were merely another service, to be
provided to all equally. It was also
ruled that all states must recognize such marriages equally, as they would
recognize any contract entered into in another state.
The decision was, from one
perspective, quite logical. But to see
marriage as merely a contact or service is to recognize only its most narrow
dimensions. In its broader theological
dimensions, marriage is not a contact, but a covenant, and even a sacrament. These are facts, and they must be emphasized,
lest the reductionist tendencies of a society overly enamored of purely legal
solutions lull us into too flat a view of civil society itself, and of what was
once referred to with no hint of irony as “holy matrimony.”
Marriage is not a mere service, to
be offered to all indiscriminately; it is not a creation of law or government,
to be defined or redefined as each generation sees fit. Ultimately, marriage is a natural thing, and
the laws we make concerning it only reflect the nature of the thing and put the
force of government behind its enablement and preservation—much as a law
forbidding murder only reflects the naturally-intuited reality that killing
another human being is wrong (although certain mitigating circumstances might
make it justified). The institution of
marriage, the crime of murder, and—to add a third, even clearer example—the law
of gravity: three examples of natural law, where our written laws about them
are more descriptive than prescriptive.
The first is as old as Eve, the second as old as Adam and the image of
God he bore, and the last is as old as the universe. Some things cannot be changed.
Legally, one can create a phenomenon
called “same-sex marriage” and require that it be recognized as a valid
contact, but such actions would not grant that relationship the fuller
dimensions of natural and sacramental marriage.
You can grant a tree a degree in mathematics, but it still won’t be able
to do sums. You can call a “ménage a
deux” of two men a “marriage” if you wish, but it still won’t be able to
produce children, or the “one flesh” union of which they are the common natural
result. Naturally and sacramentally
speaking, a marriage that produces no children is still a marriage, but a
coupling which cannot do so even in principle is not.
Theologically speaking, therefore,
it is pointless to speak of banning or requiring same-sex marriage, as it is
pointless to speak of banning antigravity rocks that fall upward. In both cases, you cannot ban the thing
because it does not exist (although I could be wrong about the rocks: there are
more things in Heaven and on Earth…).
So here is where we must make a
distinction. Along with unification
(realizing that two apparently different things share a common nature or
origin), making distinctions is one of our most powerful tools for intellectual
progress. The ancients, for example,
understood the concept of weight to be the tendency of heavier objects to fall
towards the center (read them. They are
quite clear on this). What they did not
understand was that this meant “the local center of gravitational attraction”
(in our case, Earth) and not “the center of the Universe.” They were unaware that these were two
separate things. Once they distinguished
between the two (and it was probably difficult to do this before Newton’s work
on universal gravitation), they were able to make much more sense of the
universe Copernicus had shown them: one where Earth was the center of local
gravitational attraction (i.e. the place dropped stuff falls towards), but not
the center of all.
Perhaps it is time for us likewise
to make some distinctions. The Supreme
Court’s decision was founded at least partly on an act of unification: if all
are equal, then one cannot grant a contract to couple A and deny it to couple
B. This is all well and good, so long as
it extends only to the logic of contracts.
However, we must distinguish such purely legal “marriages” from marriage
as a natural and even a sacramental thing. How, I wonder, would—or should—such
legal “marriages” differ from the previous idea of “civil unions”? I do not know, as I suspect many others do
not (do the courts?). There is much to
discuss here, and it is far too important to be short-circuited by rash legal
action or the foolish assumption that we are all already on the same page; here
civil society has a crucial role to play, I suspect, if we have the courage for
it.
Freedom of religion is an American right than
which none can be more fundamental—unless it be the right to life. The recent Supreme Court ruling must not be
used to force religious persons or organizations to violate their consciences,
canons, or creeds. Secular democracy is
a balancing act, and rarely is that act more difficult than when we are trying
to manage the relationship between church and state.
So here we are again, at the place
where church and state, law and liturgy, meet.
For some time, the question of church-state relations has repeatedly
been answered by the Church’s retreat from one area of life after another, as
the state expands into the vacuums thus created. The same thing has happened with other
aspects of civil society, even the family itself. Jefferson was right: governments tend to grow
larger, and rarely shrink. Civil society
has given up much space to government, but if government demands that the
Church yield marriage up to government monopoly, it will have demanded what the
Church can never yield.
And yet, such demands are not
necessary, if we can only learn to make some important distinctions. We must distinguish among the different
dimensions of what we call “marriage”: legal, natural, sacramental. Bearing those in mind, we can continue the
discussing of such things as “same-sex marriages” and “civil unions,” and
hopefully, we can do so in a civil manner and at a civil level. Let us hope so. A healthy democracy requires skillful
shaping, like a sculpture; but judges wield gavels, and when hammers get
involved, sculptures tend to go to pieces.
Comments
Post a Comment